Logo

Axioms and theorems of the logic

Axioms

In statements of theorems, we conventionally use letters f, g, and h to represent functions that return values that are not boolean. Letters p and q are used for predicates, in other words functions with boolean values.

Axiom 2 and axiom 3 are also shown in forms typically written when their functional parameters (f, g, h) are predicates (p, q) and have boolean values.

1) p T & p F == forall {a. p a} 2) x = y => h x = h y 2) x = y => (p x == p y) 3) (f = g) == forall {x. f x = g x} 3) (p = q) == forall {x. p x == q x} 4) {x. R} S = R[x := S] 5) the1 {x. x = y} = y

In the description of Axiom 4, the notation R[x := S] means the result of properly substituting S for x in R. Proper substitution only replaces occurrences of x that are free in the “body” (R). We say that {x. R} binds the variable x, and that x is bound in {x. R}. If R contains any bound variables, substitution in Prooftoys may also automatically rename them to avoid a phenomenon known as “capture”. See the technical notes for more details.

This process of converting {x. R} S to an equivalent term via proper substitution is known as “beta conversion”.

Definitions

Definitions including all of those used in the theorems list below. Some additional definitions are used internally or in theorems about real numbers.

All of these definitions have the form <name> = <expression> and meet the additional requirements for being safe definitions that cannot introduce contradictions into the logic.

Definitions of functions and predicates in this list are given in pairs; first the native form with only the name of the new constant on the left, and then in the traditional form. The two forms are equivalent. See the inference rules for unbinding and rebinding equations.

For more on the use of definitions in Prooftoys see the definitions page.

forall = {p. p = {x. T}} forall p == p = {x. T}
(!=) = {x. {y. not (x = y)}} x != y == not (x = y)
exists = {p. p != {x. F}} exists p == p != {x. F}
exists1 = {p. exists {x. p = {y. y = x}}} exists1 p == exists {x. p = {y. y = x}}
ident = {x. x} ident x = x
multi = {p. exists {x. exists {y. p x & p y & x != y}}} multi p == exists {x. exists {y. p x & p y & x != y}}
empty = {x. F} none = the1 empty

Theorems of the logic

There is also a “live” display of all of these theorems collected on a page here. It shows each theorem, with access to a rigorous proof verified by Prooftoys.

Basic theorems

Equality: (x = y) == (y = x) x = y & y = z => x = z
Functions ("eta conversion") {x. p x} = p

Tautologies

All tautologies can be proved, as described on this site from two slightly different points of view.

Here is a list of some tautologies that are used in Prooftoys or may be useful in building your own proofs. Remember that all uses of == can be reversed because of the symmetry of equality.

The comments suggest places where you may see these tautologies in Prooftoys proofs.

a == a (the "consider" rule) a => a (the "assume" rule) (a == b) == (b == a) (symmetry of equality/equivalence) a == (a == T) (replacing a theorem with T or T with a theorem) a & T == a
Relating "and" and "or": not (a & b) == not a | not b not (a | b) == not a & not b
Conditionals: (T => a) == a (a => F) == not a (proofs by contradiction) (a => b) & (b => c) => (a => c) ("forward" reasoning) (a => b) & (b => a) == (a == b) (proofs of equivalence) (a => b) == (not b => not a) (a => (b => c)) == (a & b => c) (managing assumptions)

Some basic quantifier laws

Unlike first-order logic, in some of these theorems are terms such as forall p. Where they exist in the list below, you can read them as for example forall {x. p x} using eta conversion if you prefer.

In this group of quantifier laws, terms such as p x or p x y inside quantifiers allow the rule to apply to any boolean term. We will discuss the reasons for this in a more advanced section, but be reassured that you can apply these theorems easily, and Prooftoys will take care of the technical details for you.

Simple quantifier rearrangement: forall {x. forall {y. p x y}} == forall {y. forall {x. p x y}} exists {x. exists {y. p x y}} == exists {y. exists {x. p x y}}
Relationship between "forall" and "exists" forall p == not (exists {x. not (p x)}) exists p == not (forall {x. not (p x)})
Reasoning with instances: forall p => p x p x => exists p